Results for 'Marcella Schmidt di Friedberg'

968 found
Order:
  1. Nature di Dio e vera religione nel pensiero di J. Smith, platonico di Cambridge.Marcella Serafini - 2004 - Filosofia Oggi 27 (108):363-400.
  2. Il mistero di Cristo nella vita dell'uomo; riflessi antropologici del Cristocentrismo di Duns Scoto.Marcella Serafini - 2010 - In Francesco Fiorentino, Lo scotismo nel Mezzogiorno d'Italia: atti del Congresso Internazionale (Bitonto 25-28, marzo 2008), in occasione del VII Centenario della morte di Giovanni Duns Scoto. Porto: Fédération internationale des instituts d'études médiévales.
  3.  12
    La libertà innata: volontà, amore e giustizia nel pensiero di Giovanni Duns Scoto.Marcella Serafini - 2022 - Roma: Città nuova.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4. Ragione e fede nel de primo principio di G. Duns Scoto.Marcella Serafini - 2003 - Miscellanea Francescana 103 (3-4):550-578.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5.  22
    Aristotle on τύχη and εὐτυχία.Marcella Linn - 2024 - Elenchos: Rivista di Studi Sul Pensiero Antico 45 (1):77-101.
    It is commonly supposed that one can build Aristotle’s account of luck (τύχη) and good fortune (εὐτυχία) from Ph. II 4–6 and Eth. Eud. VIII 2. Indeed, in these texts, he is concerned with providing a general account of each. There has, however, been some dispute on the relationship between the texts. Some argue that the two accounts conflict, and the notion of τύχη or εὐτυχία we find in the Ph. is not the one that Aristotle has in mind in (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6.  31
    (1 other version)Note di lettura. Movimenti di coscienza carichi di valore / Una cura che apre alla vita.Valeria Bizzari & Marcella D'Abbiero - forthcoming - la Società Degli Individui.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7.  37
    (1 other version)Tiziana Andina, Il Problema della Percezione nella Filosofia di Nietzsche. [REVIEW]Marcella Tarozzi Goldsmith - 2011 - New Nietzsche Studies 8 (3-4):159-164.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  11
    Le ombre della comunità: il soggetto e la realtà del mondo nella Fenomenologia dello spirito di Hegel.Marcella D'Abbiero - 1991 - Genova: Marietti.
  9.  29
    Merleau-Ponty et la Réhabilitation du Naturalisme Freudien.Gleisson Roberto Schmidt - 2015 - Chiasmi International 17:159-175.
    Dans cet article, on soutient que Merleau-Ponty, à la fin de sa production philosophique, réhabilite ontologiquement le naturalisme caractéristique à la psychanalyse freudienne. Le philosophe identifie, dans le naturalisme articulé par Freud dans sa théorie, une description de la Nature qui, contrairement au subjectivisme philosophique des philosophies de la conscience, et aussi contrairement au mécanisme causal des sciences naturelles modernes, ne favorise pas une « image fantastique de l’homme, de l’esprit et de l’histoire » contraposée à l’inexorable existence d’une Nature (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10.  35
    George Di Giovanni and H.S. Harris, eds. and annotaters., Between Kant and Hegel: Texts in the Development of Post-Kantian Idealism. [REVIEW]Dennis J. Schmidt - 1989 - International Studies in Philosophy 21 (1):75-76.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11.  55
    A lift of a theorem of Friedberg: A Banach-Mazur functional that coincides with no α-recursive functional on the class of α-recursive functions.Robert A. di Paola - 1981 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 46 (2):216-232.
    R. M. Friedberg demonstrated the existence of a recursive functional that agrees with no Banach-Mazur functional on the class of recursive functions. In this paper Friedberg's result is generalized to both α-recursive functionals and weak α-recursive functionals for all admissible ordinals α such that $\lambda , where α * is the Σ 1 -projectum of α and λ is the Σ 2 -cofinality of α. The theorem is also established for the metarecursive case, α = ω 1 , (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12.  11
    Asymptotically regular problems II: Partial Lipschitz continuity and a singular set of positive measure.Christoph Scheven & Thomas Schmidt - 2009 - Annali della Scuola Normale Superiore di Pisa- Classe di Scienze 8 (3):469-507.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13.  19
    I doni di Eustochio e Marcella: Gerolamo e la tradizione saturnalizia.Paola Francesca Moretti - 2023 - ACME: Annali della Facoltà di lettere e filosofia dell'Università degli studi di Milano 75 (2):95-108.
    In questo articolo i doni di cui Gerolamo ringrazia Eustochio e Marcella (epist. 31 e 44) sono riletti alla luce della tradizione classica dello scambio di regali, collegata specialmente ai Saturnalia: infatti, da un lato, essi trovano riscontro negli Xenia e negli Apohoreta di Marziale; dall’altro, Gerolamo, quando ne fornisce un’interpretazione, si conforma a un tipo di ricezione attiva del dono – una sua “decifrazione” –, che talora è attestata nella tradizione antica, specialmente saturnalizia (cfr. e.g. Petron. 56). In (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14. Nietzsche, Wundt e il filologo Leopold Schmidt. A proposito di una fonte della «Genealogia della morale».A. Orsucci - 1991 - Giornale Critico Della Filosofia Italiana 11 (2):275-303.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15.  18
    Alfred Schmidt.Francesco Tomasoni - 2013 - Rivista di Storia Della Filosofia 68 (4):739-751.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16.  18
    Note di lettura.Mara Meletti, Simona Bertolini, Giuseppe Turchi, Judikael Castelo Branco, Alberto Siclari & Silvano Allasia - forthcoming - la Società Degli Individui.
    Massimo Reichlin, Fondamenti di bioetica; Antonio D'Aloia, a cura di, La tempesta del Covid. Dimensioni bioetiche; Maria Zanichelli, a cura di, La persona come categoria bioetica. Prospettive umanistiche; Ferruccio Andolfi, a cura di, L'uomo e l'unico; Roberto Cipriani, L'incerta fede. Un'indagine quanti-qualitativa in Italia; Marcella D'Abbiero, Affetti privati, pubbliche virtù. La psiche come fattore politico.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17. Jurgen Habermas ed., "Antworten auf Marcuse"; Jean-Michel Palmier, "Presentation de Marcuse"; Tito Perlini, "Che cosa ha veramente detto Marcuse"; Dieter Ulle and N. Motroshlova et al., "E' rivoluzionaria la dottrina di Marcuse?". [REVIEW]Paul Piccone - 1969 - Telos: Critical Theory of the Contemporary 3.
    Herbert Marcuse; Jürgen Habermas; Alfred Schmidt; et al., "Antworten auf Herbert Marcuse." Suhrkamp, 1968. Jean-Michel Palmier, "Présentation d'Herbert Marcuse." Union générale d'éditions, 1968. Tito Perlini, "Che cosa ha veramente detto Marcuse." Ubaldini Editore, 1968. Dieter Ulle; Ju. Zemoshkin; N. Motroshlova; et al., "E' rivoluzionaria la dottrina di Marcuse?" Borla, 1969.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18. Doxastic dilemmas and epistemic blame.Sebastian Schmidt - 2024 - Philosophical Issues 34 (1):132-149.
    What should we believe when epistemic and practical reasons pull in opposite directions? The traditional view states that there is something that we ought epistemically to believe and something that we ought practically to (cause ourselves to) believe, period. More recent accounts challenge this view, either by arguing that there is something that we ought simpliciter to believe, all epistemic and practical reasons considered (the weighing view), or by denying the normativity of epistemic reasons altogether (epistemic anti‐normativism). I argue against (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  19.  77
    Facts about incoherence as non-evidential epistemic reasons.Eva Schmidt - 2023 - Asian Journal of Philosophy 2 (1):1-22.
    This paper presents a counterexample to the principle that all epistemic reasons for doxastic attitudes towards p are provided by evidence concerning p. I begin by motivating and clarifying the principle and the associated picture of epistemic reasons, including the notion of evidence concerning a proposition, which comprises both first- and second-order evidence. I then introduce the counterexample from incoherent doxastic attitudes by presenting three example cases. In each case, the fact that the subject’s doxastic attitudes are incoherent is an (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  20. Defining the method of reflective equilibrium.Michael W. Schmidt - 2024 - Synthese 203 (5):1-22.
    The method of reflective equilibrium (MRE) is a method of justification popularized by John Rawls and further developed by Norman Daniels, Michael DePaul, Folke Tersman, and Catherine Z. Elgin, among others. The basic idea is that epistemic agents have justified beliefs if they have succeeded in forming their beliefs into a harmonious system of beliefs which they reflectively judge to be the most plausible. Despite the common reference to MRE as a method, its mechanisms or rules are typically expressed in (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  21. From relational equality to personal responsibility.Andreas T. Schmidt - 2022 - Philosophical Studies 179 (4):1373-1399.
    According to relational egalitarians, equality is not primarily about the distribution of some good but about people relating to one another as equals. However, compared with other theorists in political philosophy – including other egalitarians – relational egalitarians have said relatively little on what role personal responsibility should play in their theories. For example, is equality compatible with responsibility? Should economic distributions be responsibility-sensitive? This article fills this gap. I develop a relational egalitarian framework for personal responsibility and show that (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  22.  95
    Getting Real on Rationality—Behavioral Science, Nudging, and Public Policy.Andreas T. Schmidt - 2019 - Ethics 129 (4):511-543.
    The nudge approach seeks to improve people’s decisions through small changes in their choice environments. Nudge policies often work through psychological mechanisms that deviate from traditional notions of rationality. Because of that, some critics object that nudging treats people as irrational. Such treatment might be disrespectful in itself and might crowd out more empowering policies. I defend nudging against these objections. By defending a nonstandard, ecological model of rationality, I argue that nudging not only is compatible with rational agency but (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  23. Incoherence and the balance of evidential reasons.Sebastian Https://Orcidorg Schmidt - 2023 - Asian Journal of Philosophy 2 (2):1-10.
    Eva Schmidt argues that facts about incoherent beliefs can be non-evidential epistemic reasons to suspend judgment. In this commentary, I argue that incoherence-based reasons to suspend are epistemically superfluous: if the subjects in Schmidt’s cases ought to suspend judgment, then they should do so merely on the basis of their evidential reasons. This suggests a more general strategy to reduce the apparent normativity of coherence to the normativity of evidence. I conclude with some remarks on the independent interest (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  24.  18
    (1 other version)Epistemic blame and the normativity of evidence.Sebastian Https://Orcidorg Schmidt - forthcoming - .
    The normative force of evidence can seem puzzling. It seems that having conclusive evidence for a proposition does not, by itself, make it true that one ought to believe the proposition. But spelling out the condition that evidence must meet in order to provide us with genuine normative reasons for belief seems to lead us into a dilemma: the condition either fails to explain the normative significance of epistemic reasons or it renders the content of epistemic norms practical. The first (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  25. Changing the Paradigm for Engineering Ethics.Jon Alan Schmidt - 2014 - Science and Engineering Ethics 20 (4):985-1010.
    Modern philosophy recognizes two major ethical theories: deontology, which encourages adherence to rules and fulfillment of duties or obligations; and consequentialism, which evaluates morally significant actions strictly on the basis of their actual or anticipated outcomes. Both involve the systematic application of universal abstract principles, reflecting the culturally dominant paradigm of technical rationality. Professional societies promulgate codes of ethics with which engineers are expected to comply, while courts and the public generally assign liability to engineers primarily in accordance with the (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  26. How Reasons Determine Moral Requirements.Thomas Schmidt - 2023 - In Russ Shafer-Landau, Oxford Studies in Metaethics Volume 18. Oxford University Press. pp. 97-115.
    Cases of heroic supererogation have been taken to suggest that non-moral reasons are morally relevant. While non-moral reasons are unable to make actions morally required, they can prevent moral reasons from doing so. I argue that non-moral reasons are morally relevant in yet another way, since they can also play an essential role in making it the case that an action is morally required. Even though non-moral reasons are not able themselves to make actions morally required, they can prevent reasons (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  27. (1 other version)Economic inequality and the long-term future.Andreas T. Schmidt & Daan Juijn - 2023 - Politics, Philosophy and Economics (1):67-99.
    Why, if at all, should we object to economic inequality? Some central arguments – the argument from decreasing marginal utility for example – invoke instrumental reasons and object to inequality because of its effects. Such instrumental arguments, however, often concern only the static effects of inequality and neglect its intertemporal conse- quences. In this article, we address this striking gap and investigate income inequality’s intertemporal consequences, including its potential effects on humanity’s (very) long-term future. Following recent arguments around future generations (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  28.  24
    Egalitarianism across Generations.Andreas T. Schmidt - 2024 - Utilitas 36 (3):242-264.
    Egalitarian theories assess when and why distributive inequalities are objectionable. How should egalitarians assess inequalities between generations? One egalitarian theory is (telic) distributive egalitarianism: other things being equal, equal distributions of some good are intrinsically better than unequal distributions. I first argue that distributive egalitarianism produces counterintuitive judgements when applied across generations and that attempts to discount or exclude intergenerational inequalities do not work. This being so, intergenerational comparisons also undercut the intragenerational judgements that made distributive egalitarianism intuitive in the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  29.  51
    Consequentialism and the Role of Practices in Political Philosophy.Andreas T. Schmidt - 2024 - Res Publica 30 (3):429-450.
    Political philosophers have recently debated what role social practices should play in normative theorising. Should our theories be practice-independent or practice-dependent? That is, can we formulate normative institutional principles independently of real-world practices or are such principles only ever relative to the practices they are meant to govern? Any first-order theory in political philosophy must contend with the methodological challenges coming out of this debate. In this article, I argue that consequentialism has a plausible account of how social practices should (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  30.  25
    Do we have too much choice?Andreas T. Schmidt - forthcoming - Economics and Philosophy:1-28.
    In institutional design, public policy and for society as a whole, securing freedom of choice for individuals is important. But how much choice should we aim for? Various theorists argue that above some level more choice improves neither wellbeing nor autonomy. Worse still, psychology research seems to suggest that too much choice even makes us worse off. Such reasons suggest the Sufficiency View: increasing choice is only important up to some sufficiency level, a level that is not too far from (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  31.  42
    Real‐Time Investigation of Referential Domains in Unscripted Conversation: A Targeted Language Game Approach.Sarah Brown-Schmidt & Michael K. Tanenhaus - 2008 - Cognitive Science 32 (4):643-684.
    Two experiments examined the restriction of referential domains during unscripted conversation by analyzing the modification and online interpretation of referring expressions. Experiment 1 demonstrated that from the earliest moments of processing, addressees interpreted referring expressions with respect to referential domains constrained by the conversation. Analysis of eye movements during the conversation showed elimination of standard competition effects seen with scripted language. Results from Experiment 2 pinpointed two pragmatic factors responsible for restriction of the referential domains used by speakers to design (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  32.  41
    Das Überlegungsgleichgewicht als Lebensform. Versuch zu einem vertieften Verständnis der durch John Rawls bekannt gewordenen Rechtfertigungsmethode.Michael Schmidt - 2022 - Paderborn: Brill | mentis.
    The objective of this thesis – Reflective Equilibrium as a Form of Life – is to contribute to the deepening of understanding of the method of reflective equilibrium – a method of internal epistemic justification. In the first part of the study, four paradigmatic conceptions of the method will be analyzed in order to carve out a conceptual core: The ones by John Rawls – who coined the name of the method – Norman Daniels, Michael DePaul and Catherine Elgin. I (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  33. Contingency learning without awareness: Evidence for implicit control.James R. Schmidt, Matthew J. C. Crump, Jim Cheesman & Derek Besner - 2007 - Consciousness and Cognition 16 (2):421-435.
    The results of four experiments provide evidence for controlled processing in the absence of awareness. Participants identified the colour of a neutral distracter word. Each of four words was presented in one of the four colours 75% of the time or 50% of the time . Colour identification was faster when the words appeared in the colour they were most often presented in relative to when they appeared in another colour, even for participants who were subjectively unaware of any contingencies (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  34.  81
    Consequentialism, Collective Action, and Blame.Andreas T. Schmidt - 2024 - Journal of Moral Philosophy:1-33.
    Several important questions in applied ethics – like whether to switch to a plant-based diet, reduce greenhouse gas emissions, or vote in elections – seem to share the following structure: if enough people ‘cooperate’ and become vegan for example, we bring about a better outcome; but what you do as an individual seems to make no difference whatsoever. Such collective action problems are often thought to pose a serious challenge to consequentialism. In response, I defend the Reactive Attitude Approach: rather (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  35.  64
    Criteria for unconscious cognition: Three types of dissociation.Thomas Schmidt & Dirk Vorberg - 2006 - Perception and Psychophysics 68 (3):489-504.
  36.  42
    Emotion's influence on memory for spatial and temporal context.Katherine Schmidt, Pooja Patnaik & Elizabeth A. Kensinger - 2011 - Cognition and Emotion 25 (2):229-243.
  37. Conditional Oughts and Contrastive Reasons.Thomas Schmidt - forthcoming - Philosophical Studies.
    I suggest a unified account of conditional oughts and of contrastive reasons. The core of the account is an explanation of facts about conditional oughts in terms of facts about contrastive reasons, and a reduction of contrastive reasons to non-contrastive reasons. In rejecting contrastivism about reasons, the account is consistent with orthodoxy about reasons. Moreover, it extends a standard view of how oughts and reasons are related to one another, and it makes sense of important and explanatorily recalcitrant phenomena. To (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38.  83
    Just health responsibility.H. Schmidt - 2009 - Journal of Medical Ethics 35 (1):21-26.
    Although the responsibility for health debate has intensified in several ways between Norman Daniels’ 1985 Just healthcare and Just health: meeting health needs fairly of 2008, comparatively little space is dedicated to the issue in Just health, and Daniels notes repeatedly that his account “says nothing about personal responsibility for health”. Daniels considers health responsibility mainly in a particular luck-egalitarian version which he rejects because of its potentially unfeasible, penalising and inhumane character. But I show that he nonetheless acknowledges and (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  39.  45
    Interacting with Machines: Can an Artificially Intelligent Agent Be a Partner?Philipp Schmidt & Sophie Loidolt - 2023 - Philosophy and Technology 36 (3):1-32.
    In the past decade, the fields of machine learning and artificial intelligence (AI) have seen unprecedented developments that raise human-machine interactions (HMI) to the next level.Smart machines, i.e., machines endowed with artificially intelligent systems, have lost their character as mere instruments. This, at least, seems to be the case if one considers how humans experience their interactions with them. Smart machines are construed to serve complex functions involving increasing degrees of freedom, and they generate solutions not fully anticipated by humans. (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  40.  15
    Der Diskurs des radikalen Konstruktivismus.Siegfried J. Schmidt (ed.) - 1987 - Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  41.  75
    Does collective unfreedom matter? Individualism, power and proletarian unfreedom.Andreas T. Schmidt - 2023 - Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 26 (6):964-985.
    When assessing institutions and social outcomes, it matters how free society is within them (‘societal freedom’). For example, does capitalism come with greater societal freedom than socialism? For such judgements, freedom theorists typically assume Individualism: societal freedom is simply the aggregate of individual freedom. However, G.A. Cohen’s well-known case provides a challenge: imagine ten prisoners are individually free to leave their prison but doing so would incarcerate the remaining nine. Assume further that no one actually leaves. If we adopt Individualism (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  42.  34
    David Hume: Reason in History.Claudia M. Schmidt - 2003 - Pennsylvania State University Press.
    In his seminal _Philosophy of David Hume_, Norman Kemp Smith called for a study of Hume "in all his manifold activities: as philosopher, as political theorist, as economist, as historian, and as man of letters," indicating that "Hume's philosophy, as the attitude of mind that found for itself these various forms of expression, will then have been presented, adequately and in due perspective, for the first time." Claudia Schmidt seeks to address this long-standing need in Hume scholarship. Against the (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  43. Introduction: Towards an Ethics of Mind.Sebastian Schmidt - 2020 - In Sebastian Schmidt & Gerhard Ernst, The Ethics of Belief and Beyond: Understanding Mental Normativity. Abingdon, UK: Routledge. pp. 1-20.
    This chapter locates our overall approach within the dialectic of contemporary philosophical debates and provides an overall framework for discussion. First, I introduce the problem of mental normativity. I show how this problem poses a prima facie threat to the common assumption in epistemology and metaethics that beliefs and other attitudes are governed by robust normative requirements. Secondly, I motivate philosophical inquiry about an ethics of mind by tracing this field back to recent debates in the ethics of belief. I (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  44.  9
    Kommentar zu Nietzsches "Die Geburt der Tragödie".Jochen Schmidt - 2012 - De Gruyter.
    Mazzino Montinari nannte Die Geburt der Tragödie "Nietzsches schwierigstes Werk". Es greift auf antike Traditionen zurück und orientiert sich weltanschaulich an Schopenhauer und Wagner, dessen,Musikdrama' Nietzsche als "Wiedergeburt der Tragödie"darstellt. Bei Nietzsche selbst und in der Kulturkritik wirkte vor allem das Konzept des Dionysischen nach. Gegen die Décadence gerichtet, wurde es zum Ideogramm eines rauschhaften Lebenskults.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  45.  23
    7 Kant on Trolleys and Autonomous Driving.Elke Elisabeth Schmidt - 2022 - In Hyeongjoo Kim & Dieter Schönecker, Kant and Artificial Intelligence. De Gruyter. pp. 189-222.
  46.  8
    (1 other version)Der Begriff der Natur in der Lehre von Marx.Alfred Schmidt - 1962 - [Frankfurt a.M.]: Europäische Verlagsanstalt.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  47. Does Perceptual Content Have to Be Objective? A Defence of Nonconceptualism.Eva Schmidt - 2015 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 46 (1):201-214.
    In this paper, I discuss the conceptualist claim that we cannot speak of perceptual content unless we assume it is objective content. The conceptualist argues that only conceptual content can meet the requirement of being objective, so that the view that perceptual experience has nonconceptual content is not tenable. I start out by presenting the argument from objectivity as it can be found in McDowell. I then present the following objections: First, perceptual objectivity cannot be due to the perceiver’s conception (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  48.  72
    Frontal brain electrical activity distinguishes valence and intensity of musical emotions.Louis A. Schmidt & Laurel J. Trainor - 2001 - Cognition and Emotion 15 (4):487-500.
  49.  71
    Children’s developing metaethical judgments.Marco F. H. Schmidt, Ivan Gonzalez-Cabrera & Michael Tomasello - 2017 - Journal of Experimental Child Psychology 164:163-177.
    Human adults incline toward moral objectivism but may approach things more relativistically if different cultures are involved. In this study, 4-, 6-, and 9-year-old children (N = 136) witnessed two parties who disagreed about moral matters: a normative judge (e.g., judging that it is wrong to do X) and an antinormative judge (e.g., judging that it is okay to do X). We assessed children’s metaethical judgment, that is, whether they judged that only one party (objectivism) or both parties (relativism) could (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  50.  43
    Freedom of choice and the tobacco endgame.Andreas T. Schmidt - 2021 - Bioethics 36 (1):77-84.
    Endgame proposals strive for a tobacco‐free (or at least cigarette‐free) society. Some endgame proposals are radical and include, for example, a complete ban on cigarettes. Setting aside empirical worries, one worry is ethical: would such proposals not go too far in interfering with individual freedom? I argue that concerns around freedom do not speak against endgame proposals, including strong proposals such as a ban on cigarettes. I first argue that when balancing freedom with public health goals in tobacco control, the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
1 — 50 / 968